Based on a recommendation by a student that was prompted while teaching Harman’s Prince of Networks, my bedtime reading has recently consisted of Jared Diamond’s Guns, Germs, and Steel: The Fate of Human Societies. Although I’m not very far into the book, so far I am very much enjoying it. Like Braudel and the Annales School historians, Diamond is extremely attentive to the role played by nonhuman objects in collectives. In many respects, Diamond’s Guns, Germs, and Steel reads like a much quicker and livelier version of Braudel’s Capitalism & Civilization. Diamond, I think, presents us with what 1/3 of an object-oriented analysis would look like in social and political thought. Speaking of the encounter between Pizarro and Atahuallpa, Daimond writes:
How did Pizarro come to be at Cajamarca? Why didn’t Atahuallpa instead try to conquer Spain? Pizarro came to Cajamarka by means of European maritime technology, which built the ships that took him across the Atlantic from Spain to Panama, and then in the Pacific from Panama to Peru. Lacking such technology, Atahuallpa did not expand overseas out of South America.
In addition to the ships themselves, Pizarro’s presence depended on the centralized political organization that enabled Spain to finance, build, staff, and equip the ships. The Inca Empire also had a centralized political organization, but that actually worked to its disadvantage, because Pizarro seized the Inca chain of command intact by capturing Atahuallpa. Since the Inca bureaucracy was so strongly identified with its god-like absolute monarch, it disintegrated after Atahuallpa’s death. Maritime technology coupled with political organization was similarly essential for European expansions to other continents, as well as for expansion of many other peoples.
A related factor bringing Spaniards to Peru was the existence of writing. Spain possessed it, while the Inca Empire did not. Information could be spread far more widely, more accurately, and in more detail by writing than it could be transmitted by mouth. That information, coming back to Spain from Columbus’s voyages and from Cortes’s conquest of Mexico, sent Spaniards pouring into the New World. Letters and pamphlets supplied both the motivation and the necessary detailed sailing directions. The first published report of Pizarro’s exploits, by his companion Captian Cristobal de Mena, was printed in Seville in April 15 1534, a mere nine months after Atahuallpa’s execution. It became a best-seller, was rapidly translated into other European language, and sent a further stream of Spanish colonists to tighten Pizarro’s grip on Peru. (78 – 79)
Daimond works not with the concept of society, which is a concept restricted to people and their beliefs, but rather with what Latour calls collectives. Collectives are entanglements of objects. They can be entanglements composed entirely of nonhuman objects as in the case of an eco-system, or they can be entanglements that also contain humans as well as nonhuman objects. However, they can never be composed of humans alone. In his analysis of the encounter between Spain and South America, Daimond not only discusses human actors such as Atahuallpa, but also institutions like forms of political organization, and nonhuman actors such as germs, clubs, forms of armor, maritime technologies, writing, pamphlets, letters, horses, and so on. All of these entities are full blown actors in Diamond’s account that are generative of certain forms of association or certain social relations.
Indeed, when Diamond begins discussing food production in Europe, he notes the manner in which the domestication of plants and animal led to markedly different forms of human relation:
All those are direct ways in which plant and animal domestication led to denser human populations by yielding more food than did the hunter-gatherer lifestyle. A more indirect way involved the consequences of the sedentary lifestyle enforced by food production. People of many hunter-gatherer societies move frequently in search of wild foods, but farmers must remain near their fields and orchards. The resulting fixed abode contributes to denser human populations by permitting a shortened birth interval. A hunter-gather mother who is shifting camp can carry only one child, along with her few possessions. She cannot afford to bear her next child until the previous toddler can walk fast enough to keep up with the tribe and not hold it back. In practice, nomadic hunter-gatherers space their children about four years apart by means of lactational amenorrhea, sexual abstinence, infanticide, and abortion. By contrast, sedentary people, unconstrained by problems of carrying young children on treks, can bear and raise as many children as they can feed. The birth interval for many farm peoples is around two years, half that of hunter-gatherers. That higher birthrate of food producers, together with their ability to feed more people per acre, lets them achieve much higher population densities than hunter-gatherers.
A separate consequence of a settled existence is that it permits one to store food surpluses, since storage would be pointless if one didn’t remain nearby to guard the stored food. While some nomadic hunter-gathers may occasionally bag more food than they can consume in a few days, such a bonanza is of little use to them because they cannot protect it. But stored food is essential for feeding non-food-producing specialists, and certainly for supporting whole towns of them. Hence nomadic hunter-gatherer societies have few or no such full-time specialists, who instead first appear in sedentary societies.
Two types of such specialists are kings and bureaucrats. Hunter-gatherer societies tend to be relatively egalitarian, to lack full-time bureaucrats and hereditary chiefs, and to have small-scale political organization at the level of the band of tribe. That’s because all able-bodied hunter-gatherers are obliged to devote much of their time to acquiring food. In contrast, once food can be stockpiled, a political elite can gain control of food produced by others, assert the right of taxation, escape the need to feed itself, and engage full-time in political activities. Hence moderate-sized agricultural societies are often organized in chiefdoms, and kingdoms are confined to large agricultural societies. Those complex political units are much better able to mount a sustained war of conquest than in an egalitarian band of hunters. (89 – 90)
I quote these passages at length because they are so foreign to most of what we find in dominant strains of continental cultural, social, and political theory. Daimond’s history is a history of collectives that is as much a history of the role played by nonhuman objects as human actants in the genesis of associations between humans and nonhumans in these collectives. Ask yourself honestly, do you really see anything remotely like a discussion of these sorts of agencies in the social and political thought of the Frankfurt School, Zizek, Ranciere, Balibar, Laclau, Derrida, or Badiou? Stepping outside the continental tradition, do you find it in Rawls or Habermas? What about Luhmann? No, we find nothing remotely close to the discussion of these issues. Rather, to encounter a discussion of the role of these sorts of actors we need to turn to Latour and the ANT theorists, Marx, Deleuze and Guattari and their under-developed analysis of machinic assemblages, and thinkers like McLuhan, Castelles, Haraway, DeLanda, Hayles, Bogost, Ong, Kittler, and so on.
What are we missing as a result of ignoring these nonhuman actors, and to what degree are our questions of political theory and action poorly formed and premised on a complete misrecognition of why collective formations are as they are? Indeed, to what degree do we entirely miss issues that are political because we have restricted the domain of the political to the human and the subject? To a great degree, I would say. However, as I said at the beginning of this post, something like Diamond’s analysis only constitutes 1/3 of what an OOO analysis would look like in social and political thought. Diamond is to be commended for paying keen attention to the role played by nonhuman actants in collectives that contain humans, but we must also recall that for OOO signs and language are objects as well. The semiotic is not to be abandoned. What is to be abandoned is the thesis of the linguistic idealists to the effect that language and signs constitute entities. Rather, we must think the manner in which the semiotic is entangled with non-semiotic actants. And finally, we need to make room for the manner in which objects are always withdrawn or in excess of any of their manifestations or sensuous presentations. A fullblown OOO analysis would contain all three of these dimensions in its thinking of collectives and entanglements.
May 13, 2010 at 6:49 pm
[…] May 13, 2010 I ought to be pressuring Levi to finish The Democracy of Objects (which I eagerly await) not cheer on his blog posts. But he’s been on a roll in recent days, and has just posted ONE OF MY FAVORITE LARVAL SUBJECTS POSTS EVER. […]
May 13, 2010 at 8:06 pm
Good grief Levi, I have two book projects under way (very early stages), both OOO related, and with this post you make me think that Diamond may have beat me to it – at least thematically – with one of them. Its that old PhD paranoia resurfacing, thinking that someone, somewhere in the world, is working on precisely what you are doing, and will get there first.
The only Diamond book I have on my shelf is The Rise and Fall of the Third Chimpanzee, I suspect I will now have to check this one out.
Great post by the way, its actually likely to help me describe one of my book proposals for an internal bid for teaching relief. Always interesting trying to translate OOO for different academic audiences. My Head of Humanities, a historian, gets it and is interested in the possibilities, our director of research, though, was struggling yesterday.
May 13, 2010 at 8:19 pm
Hi Levi,
I agree that Diamond’s emphasis on material things is most welcome when compared to traditional (anthropocentric) history. I’m a little less sanguine about his work because I’ve read so many critiques by those who know the details better than he does (anthropologists, archaeologists, geographers, et al) – which is probably even more the case with his later book Collapse. But his approach, esp. in Guns, Germs & Steel, resonates with the kind of approaches Latour and others (and OOO) have been articulating. Diamond is, at the very least, a popularizer of some useful ways of thinking.
I also agree with Graham that DeLanda, esp. his Thousand Years of Nonlinear History, should be added to the “good” list. The field of environmental history has been trying to do this sort of thing for a while, and getting better at it over time (e.g., Richard White’s The Organic Machine: The Remaking of the Columbia River). “Big history” (as in David Christian’s Maps of Time) is also moving in this direction. And the themes of materiality and the “social life of things” have been growing in anthropology (e.g., Daniel Miller, Appadurai), sociology (Scott Lash & Celia Lury), geography (see eg. Harrison, Pile, & Thrift’s Patterned Ground), archaeology, and of course science studies (Latour, Law, Mol, Barad, Haraway, Hayles, et al). Philosophers have been lagging well behind this curve (with a few exceptions) so it’s great to see that that’s now changing. And it’s useful for me to be reminded of that philosophical gap – it’s a good reason for me not to get too caught up in critiquing “objects.” There’s a place for careful philosophizing of the relations between all these things, and I see now that that’s what you and Graham, among others, are trying to do. It’s much needed work (which is why I’m eagerly awaiting your Democracy of Objects!).
Cheers,
Adrian
May 13, 2010 at 8:19 pm
Although I have not read this particular book by Diamond I have read parts of his book ”Collapse”. Being an archaeologist myself, I am quite familiar with this kind of writing. Diamond’s writings is quite similar to much archaeological literature during the 1960s and 70s (what tend to be called processual archaeology, a more positivistic and functionalistic view of the past). I have summarized Joseph Tainter’s critique of Diamond and three other “collapse” authors: http://haecceities.wordpress.com/2009/04/21/climate-and-the-%e2%80%9cmaya-collapse%e2%80%9d-pt-2-irresponsible-authors/
Yes, Diamond does include collectives of objects in his discussion but he is using quite simplistic models and very generalized views of both anthropological and archaeological data. For example, the term hunter-gatherer used in the quote above is incredibly coarse and include a wide range of different collectives (check Tim Ingold for a critique of these categorizations which are the remains of 19th century culture evolutionary ideas). In the quote we find yet other complicated terms which are ideal types, such as chiefdom (I honestly have no idea what a “chiefdom” is because few fit the definitions). Diamond still maintains the idea that the world consists of cultures (European, Inca, Maya, etc.). These terms ultimately falls back on an essence, or a master-signifier, that defines every single artifact. Hence, “European maritime technology”, suggests something different than “Arabic” or “Chinese” maritime technology. It is a European cultural essence buried within that term. Diamond is still too anthropocentric or rather culturecentred. Although culture includes objects these objects are defined by a transcendent concept of culture, not the other way around.
May 13, 2010 at 8:35 pm
Žižek talks of trash as an aesthetic object in Astra Taylors film and book Examined life. He says “whenever we are engaged with the world we use objects. It is, for me, always a mysterious moment when you see an object that was originally a functional object, part of our system of needs, as no longer of any use, changed into trash.”
At that moment he is standing knee deep in refuse. He goes on to talk about finding meaning in ‘useless objects.’ It seems that difference here between OOO and Žižek is the connotations of useless. Žižek wants to make an ideological leap into exploring the world of ecology from the point of the subject and you want to embrace the point of view of the object. Seeing trash from both points of view is enlightening.
Russell
May 13, 2010 at 8:39 pm
This is an interesting post in that it might well be the first review I’ve read of the book that takes the form of: this is doing good work, but is not quite right (rather, it’s 1/3 right).
Alas, the reaction it’s received from the circles who don’t typically treat nonhuman objects has been predictable and boring, and doesn’t seem to point to any sort of likely advancement of the debate. One flurry of articles makes the expected charges of “environmental determinism”, and another flurry of articles accuses Diamond of being a racist colonialist. (Some do both, for good measure.)
May 13, 2010 at 9:01 pm
Hi Russell,
That sounds right. I would add the caveat that the treatment of objects in terms of use is already a correlationist gesture because the object has been treated in terms of its status as a vehicle for human intentions. This renders the object invisible. What’s interesting about Diamond’s analysis is that he treats objects themselves as being genuine actors and places emphasis on the unintended and aleatory.
May 13, 2010 at 9:06 pm
Johan,
I’m on Latour’s side in his thesis that the anthropologists tend to be on the right side by virtue of the role they attribute to nonhuman actants (he claims this in We Have Never Been Modern). Your points here are well taken but I also think they’re somewhat besides the point. What is valuable in Diamond’s book is the manner in which he diminishes the role played by cultural explanation (references to human symbols, signs, beliefs, etc), and emphasizes the role played by nonhuman actants in generating and influencing associations between humans. In my view, any critique of this style of analysis should be taken with a grain of salt unless the theorist developing the critique has suitably given a central place to the role played by nonhuman actors in his own work. Absent this, I suspect it’s likely that such critiques are the product of correlationist assumptions and styles of thought that are largely missing the point. However, as I said in the post, what Diamond is up to is only a 1/3 of what an object-oriented analysis would like to do. In addition to this an OOO analysis would make room for the semiotic and the withdrawal of objects.
May 13, 2010 at 9:24 pm
Hey Adrian,
I was in a rush when writing the post this weekend, which probably accounts for why I forgot to add ecophilosophy to the “good” list. I think there are certain forms of contemporary theory that are inevitably led to take into account the role played by nonhuman actants. Among these would be ecophilosophy, good forms of media study that investigate not only the content of media, but also the mediums themselves, and a good deal of Anglo-American feminist thought that doesn’t focus on the signifier alone.
To be quite honest I don’t understand what the debate over relations is all about. Relations are all over the place in OOO. All OOO once to emphasize is that objects are external to their relations or, to put it positively, that objects can enter into different relations. It’s internalism that OOO rejects, not relations as such.
I agree that philosophy is very much behind the curve on these things and with your points about Diamond and popularization. I defer to the historians and anthropologists on the actual details and accuracy of his claims. What’s important is the central role he attributes to nonhuman actants in collectives involving humans. I evoke the book and some representative passages to give readers a sense of what an OOO approach would, in part, look like in social and political thought. I get the sense that these kinds of actants are not even on the radar for a lot of critical theorists. We forget that something as simple as writing or a letter– not the content, but its brute material existents –brings human actors together in an entirely different way than speech. These unobtrusive actants (Latour would say they’re “blackboxed” I guess) play a massive role in collectives where humans exist.
Today I was watching Modern Marvels on, of all things, supermarkets. One of the points the show made is that the rise of the supermarket took place at precisely the right time because of the invention of the refrigerator and the automobile. When we talk about environmental issues, how many of us think about the suburbs and refrigerators as key players in our environmental problems? The automobile creates the possibility of moving to the suburbs and commuting to world. This, in turn, creates the problem of having enough food on hand because you can’t walk around the corner to the market. The refrigerator, in its turn, allows for the storage of surpluses of food. Again, a network of black boxes we hardly notice that enable a particular kind of collective and that play into the heart of environmental problems. All invisible unless you have the right conceptual tools to assist you in seeing them.
May 13, 2010 at 9:31 pm
[…] does he turn to non-human actors and/or collectives in the way that Latour argues we must do. Larval subjects recently made just this point specifically against Derrida’s (and others’) social and political […]
May 13, 2010 at 9:40 pm
Hans Zinsser’s Rats, Lice and History, which was first published in 1934 – and has been in print ever since – is an excellent example of non-human centered history. It’s billed as a “biography” of the typhus bacterium, and it’s a story in which rats and lice are at least as import as humans.
May 13, 2010 at 9:54 pm
You may find Crosby’s Ecological Imperialism of interest. It’s sort of the more academic version of Diamond’s book, but shorter and with a focus on ecosystems.
May 13, 2010 at 10:03 pm
Thanks for the reference, Anthony. I’ll definitely check it out!
May 14, 2010 at 5:48 am
I do not think my viewpoint is beside the point. Indeed, there are plenty of correlationist assumptions among people criticising Diamond (see McAnany and Yoffee’s “Questioning Collapse: Human Resilience, Ecological Vulnerability, & the Aftermath of Empire”).
My point is that Diamond still is following an anthropocentric and culturecentred view even if he emphasize nonhuman actants. It is after all “the Maya culture” that collapses, etc. Even if he shows how nonhuman actants affect collectives, his emphasis is still how they in the end affect people and their “societies” or “civilizations”.
A problem I do have with Diamond is that the various terms of collectives that he uses have quite different origins. The Easter Islanders are defined by living on an island. The “Maya culture” that he discusses is a construction based on linguistics (are they then comparable objects of study?). All other data (artifacts, architecture, rituals, etc.) have been squeezed into these rather arborescent structures (Easter Island culture and Maya culture). These cultures are objects created by archaeologists or historians, but did they exist as true objects in the past rather than being objects of current disciplines?
In short: Diamond also uses correlationist assumptions but not to the same extent as his critiques. His kind of writing is quite common in archaeology, a discipline that by its “nature” has to rely on objects. The main problem, however, and this what I tried to say, is that these objects are always integrated into past cultures, an anthropocentric frame (and Diamond is a perfect example of this).
May 14, 2010 at 8:01 am
The automobile creates the possibility of moving to the suburbs and commuting to world.
An awesome typo, yes?
May 14, 2010 at 12:41 pm
One way of approaching the, I think, quite legitimate reservations that Johan raises is to recognise (and this should be quite obvious really) that just because we’ve got a noun for something doesn’t mean we should take it to be an object!
To use words like ‘European, Inca, Maya, European maritime technology’ do not necessarily make a work ‘object oriented’ – this is too hasty a conclusion. Whether a ‘culture’ or a ‘nation’ or a ‘state’ can be legitimately referred to as an ‘object’ at all I think is a very important point.
I study international relations and it is of the utmost importance to the theory of this discipline whether one accepts the state and thus the international system to be closed, black-boxed ‘objects’ (as the dominant, mainstream neo-positivist theories hold) or whether it is actually necessary to insist on opening up this black-box and actually denying it closure (both for ontological and ethical reasons). Similar concerns are routinely raised about Diamond’s histories and I think an OOO driven social science needs to address these problems as problems head on not just accuse critics of correlationism.
I think the problem with Diamond’s work is not that it is oriented towards objects (which is good) but that it is (like Braudel and McNeill certainly) overwhelmingly macro-oriented; this is not necessarily a bad thing but it is certainly something with a lot of problems attached to it.
If we are to advance object oriented theory into the humanities and social sciences further (and this is very much my intention) we need to square some circles. For example, are not the histories of Diamond et al. not the absolute anti-thesis of Latour’s ANT? (And is not Latour’s ANT somewhat the cause celebre of object oriented approaches in the social sciences so far?)
Being ‘object oriented’ doesn’t necessarily forgive one all other sins. I don’t think one need be ‘correlationist’ to recognise the problems of macro-history. That isn’t to dismiss its relevance, however, just to insist on the recognition of its problems.
May 14, 2010 at 2:00 pm
[…] May 14, 2010 Some Remarks on Latour, Mereology, and Actants Posted by larvalsubjects under Abstraction, Agency, Analysis, Antagonism, Assemblages, Emergence, Graham Harman, Individuation, Latour, Object-Oriented Philosophy Leave a Comment Responding to my post on Diamond, Yant writes: […]
May 19, 2010 at 1:41 pm
[…] What if: Experience | May 19, 2010 Treatment of objects in terms of use is already a correlationist gesture because the object has been treated in terms of its status as a vehicle for human intentions. This renders the object invisible. Levi Bryant […]
May 23, 2010 at 11:04 pm
[…] on Levi’s suggestion, I just recently started reading Guns, Germs, and Steel, by Jared Diamond, as the first of some […]