One of the more interesting things to watch in the debates surround OOO in the last couple of years is how strongly people react to the term “object”. For many, the concept of “object” seems to embody all that is bad or wrong in human thought. As a consequence, we are told that we must replace the concept of object with that of process and event. Objects, it is said, do not become, but just sit there, doing nothing. What a strange carry over from Greek thought!
The Greeks distinguished between those things that have psyche and those things that do not have psyche. Psyche, of course, would later become “soul”. Psyche refers to a principle of motion things contain within themselves. If a rock lacks psyche, then this is because it is unable to move itself. Rather, the rock relies on something else to move it. If, by contrast, plants have psyche then this is because they grow of their own accord. Likewise, animals have psyche because they both grow, but also have appetite, mobility, and perception. Finally, humans have psyche because they grow, have appetite, mobility, perception, and reason or the capacity to direct themselves. In a strange passage in “The Letter to Menoeceus“, Epicurus will say that we know the gods exist because we can see them. No doubt he is referring to the planets, known in Greek as asteres planetai or “astral wanderers”. In their wandering throughout the night sky, the planets suggested living beings, because random movement, as we know from our cats and children, is suggestive of the presence of psyche. Objects without psyche, it will be said, are passive entities, whereas those with psyche are active entities.
This is such a strange position to advocate, especially in an atomic age where we now know that objects of all kinds are swarming with movement. Even Lucretius had the good sense to notice that this distinction had to be based on a form of folk ontology. As Lucretius writes in a remarkable passage from De Rerum Natura,
Herein wonder not
How ’tis that, while the seeds of things are all
Moving forever, the sum yet seems to stand
Supremely still, except in cases where
A thing shows motion of its frame as whole.
For far beneath the ken of senses lies
The nature of those ultimates of the world;
And so, since those themselves thou canst not see,
Their motion also must they veil from men-
For mark, indeed, how things we can see, oft
Yet hide their motions, when afar from us
Along the distant landscape. Often thus,
Upon a hillside will the woolly flocks
Be cropping their goodly food and creeping about
Whither the summons of the grass, begemmed
With the fresh dew, is calling, and the lambs
Well filled, are frisking, locking horns in sport:
Yet all for us seem blurred and blent afar-
A glint of white at rest on a green hill. (Book II)
From afar, notes Lucretius, the sheep look as if they are not moving at all. But were we to closely approach them, we would discover that they are frolicking about, taking little nips of dewy grass and playfully dancing about with one another. And so it is, argues Lucretius, with all objects. Although the rock over there appears to sit still, it is in a constant state of motion or activity. Spoken like a true onticologist! The important difference here would be that where for Lucretius there are ultimate and indivisible units (the famous atoms), for OOO there are no final units. It’s turtles all the way down without any primordial turtles.
read on!
Here I’ll just lay out some of my claims about the being of objects, without defending or arguing for those claims (you’ll find those arguments in The Democracy of Objects). Within the framework of my onticology, there are only objects, properties, and relations. While objects differ from one another– a cat is certainly different than a rock –they all fall under the category of objects. As such, I do not begin from a fundamental split between subjects on the one hand and objects on the other hand. An object is not what stands in opposition to a subject. Indeed, subjects themselves are, for me, a type of object. They are particularly important objects for us insofar as we happen to be subjects, yet metaphysically they are no more or less an object than anything else.
I conceive objects as autopoietic and allopoietic machines as outlined by Maturana and Varela, but above all by Niklas Luhmann. The major difference between Luhmann’s account of autopoietic and allopoietic machines and Maturana and Varela’s is that the latter conceives these machines as essentially homeostatic, functioning in such a way as to maintain a particular equilibrium and structural identity across time, whereas Luhmann’s machines can only reproduce themselves through novelty. If information is the difference that makes a difference, then information repeated twice is no longer information. Consequently, if objects or objectiles are to maintain their existence across time, they must perpetually renew themselves through the production of novel events. A key feature of these autopoietic and allopoietic machines is that they maintain themselves through the production of events. The time of the object is a time in which the components of that object or machine must (re)produce its components from moment to moment. It is this processuality that constitutes the substantiality of objects. It is this process through which an object (re)produces itself that is the being of an object. Far from being something that just sits there as the Greeks had it in their folk ontology, these machines are ongoing activities. If these machines are nonetheless objects, then this is because there is a unity to this process that renders them discrete entities in their own right. These processes, as it were, are the “substantial form” of the machine or object. A key point that follows from this is that objects are not identical to its parts. The parts of an object come and go, sometimes getting destroyed, at other times moving out of the object and landing elsewhere, while that substantial form, that processuality, remains. If that’s not “evental” and “processual” enough for you, I just don’t know what you’re asking for.
A crucial feature of objects is that by virtue of being dynamic systems (autopoietic and allopoietic machines) that must (re)produce themselves from moment to moment, objects perpetually face the problem of entropy. The life of an object is such that it is always a question of how it can get to the next event. How is it that an object can produce the next event, the next components, that will allow it to continue its adventure or life through time for a moment longer? In this regard, objects are perpetually disintegrating and are perpetually facing the threat of disintegration. Objects are perpetually disintegrating because the past events of which they were composed, their past components, disappear in the order of time. Objects use these disintegrating events, in part, as fodder to create new events. In this respect, objectiles very much resemble Whitehead’s actual occasions, where past actual occasions are used in the production of subsequent actual occasions. The major difference would be that for me every object is what is called a society. Objects perpetually face the threat of entropy or disintegration because, in subsequent phases of the object the process or activity can always fall apart. The substantial form that animates the object can fail or fall apart in much the same way that a hurricane or tornado is unable to sustain itself after a time, leading the object to fall apart like smoke diffusing in the wind.
Objects thus “use” their entropy as a way of (re)producing themselves, but perpetually face the threat of entropy from the outside. What distinguishes different types of objects is thus not whether they are processual or not, but rather the degree of negentropy they enjoy. Rocks, for example, enjoy a relatively low degree of negentropy. They hold themselves together by a variety of forces, but engage in a very low degree of activity in (re)producing themselves. Hurricanes, by contrast, have a high degree of negentropy, reproducing their structure or pattern in the order of time from prior events. Likewise with living bodies and social systems.
Suppose we take the theory blogosphere as an example of an object to illustrate these points. The theory blogosphere differentiates itself into a variety of different networks that take on the status of being an object in their own right. Thus, for example, one of these objects would be composed of my blog coupled with Graham’s blog coupled with Morton’s blog coupled with Dark Chemistry, Anomalous Monism, Immanence blog, An Un-Canny Ontology, Digital Digs, Bogost’s blog, Archive Fire, Shaviro’s blog, etc., etc., etc. Each of these blogs is itself an object and a part of a larger object. This larger object is only able to exist through the perpetual production of events. In order for this larger object to exist– let’s call it “the SR blog object” –the individual blogs must update themselves or produce new posts and comments. Yet this is only a necessary condition, not a sufficient condition. In addition to this, the blogs must link to one another, interact with one another, and respond to one another. In this way, a certain unity emerges that takes on the form of an object in its own right.
Hopefully it will be noticed just how little an autopoietic object like the SR-blog-object resembles the homeostatic objects of Maturana and Varela. In order to reproduce itself, the SR-blog-object requires the production of novelty, of new events, rather than the repetition of one and the same structure. In the absence of the production of novelty, the SR-blog-object withers and dies as it’s left without the means to get from one event to another in the order of time. We’re blog posts just to repeat themselves over and over again, events would cease to be produced. It will also be noted that the parts (individual blogs) of the SR-blog-object enjoy a very strange status with respect to the SR-blog-objects. Occasionally some blogs fall silent. Nate’s blog, for example, was silent for a very long time. Recently, Graham’s blog has become almost entirely about the events taking place in the Middle East, not SR or OOO. The parts that make up the SR-blog-object flicker in and out of existence, contributing here, not contributing there, and so on. Yet the SR-blog-object continues to persist despite this flickering of the individual blogs that make it up. Similarly, the individual blogs that make up the SR-blog-object can also be parts of other larger scale objects. Thus, for example, Jeff Bell’s Anomalous Monism sometimes contributes events to the SR-blog-object, allowing that object to continue its journey throughout time, while at other times it contributes to what is perhaps a “Deleuze-blog-object”. The parts of an object can, in a number of instances, belong to a variety of distinct objects.
From the foregoing, it is clear that objects are dynamic, historical, and becoming. The SR-blog-object evolves over time as a function of the events that occur within it. As a consequence, it is a dynamic and shifting system as a consequence of the events through which it (re)produces itself. One intriguing feature of the SR-blog-object is that it is also a historical system. Like a space-time worm, the SR-blog-object carries its past behind it as a part of its being. This, in part, accounts for the creativity of such an object. Past events can be resurrected, becoming fodder for new discussions and posts, but now in different contexts and frames. As a result, this object grows more complex over time as it is not governed simply by the surface interactions taking place in the present, but also takes its own past as a factor in its overcoming of entropy so as to produce new subsequent events.
Finally, objects are operationally closed but dynamically open. “Operational closure” is one of the terms I use for withdrawal. Objects are operationally closed insofar as they never encounter other objects directly, but always as a function of their own internal organization. When events take place in the world outside of the SR-blog-object, these events can perturb that object in a variety of ways, but the information that the SR-blog-object produces as a result of these perturbations will not be a function of the external events themselves, but of the internal organization of the SR-blog-object. Every object always encounters the world under conditions of closure, translating it in its own particular way. However, objects are nonetheless dynamically open insofar as these perturbation provide impetus for the evolution and development of objects, contributing to their growing complexity over time.
March 2, 2011 at 8:21 pm
Thanks Levi. I’m particularly interested in your discussion of time. When you say “How is it that an object can produce the next event, the next components, that will allow it to continue its adventure or life through time for a moment longer?” I am curious if view time as a kind of medium through which objects move or if you view time as more localized and relational. Maybe that’s not either/or. It could certainly be both or neither. I would imagine that time would be like space: a dimension produce through relation. Not sure though.
BTW, I find your use of operational closure thought-provoking. I keep asking myself, if objects withdraw from themselves, what do they close upon? Would objects exceed their own closure?
March 2, 2011 at 8:37 pm
I think there is some crossover here on my thoughts regarding Algorithms and execution. Might we worth outlining this in a future post.
I like the fact that you also use the term ‘significant form’ to describe the unity of objects. This is where my formalist brain kicks in and says ‘formalists have been here before’, but of course, not the scale that OOO argues is willing to argue.
I’d like to know a bit more about objects as ‘historical systems’ Is it elaborated in DOO?
March 2, 2011 at 9:24 pm
Hi Robert,
I had meant to get to you and Ian on the operationality of objects, but a slew of things were going on as I wrote this so it kinda slipped out of my mind. Objects constitute their own elements or parts in reproducing themselves. It’s here that I see operationality entering the picture. Operations would be the mechanism by which objects produce those components or events that allow them to maintain themselves in the order of time.
I don’t spend a lot of time discussing historical systems in TDO, though much of what I have in mind is already outlined in the sections on memory in my first book, Difference and Givenness. Very roughly, a historical system would be a system whose past remains available to it as a source for potential inputs. Historical systems are thus systems that simultaneously record their events as they produce them. These traces can then be used as subsequent inputs for further operations of the object across time. In non-historical systems the past just disappears. In historical systems, the past is preserved. Thus, for example, a rock does not record the event of being put in my daughter’s mouth in such a way that it can retrieve this event ten years from now. By contrast, something that happened to you or me ten years ago can very much be operative in our present in an unconscious or conscious way. Living systems, social systems, and increasingly computer technologies seem to have these characteristics.
March 2, 2011 at 9:29 pm
Strange, I was reworking some readings of Harman’s early Doctoral dissertation, and your idea of the SR blog object seems to have had an asymmetrical corollary. I was working through his sense of an object not being a solid or static thing, but of being an object-effect instead:
This idea of the object or entity we name bridge being itself a bridge-effect, and being a force that generates a world is at the heart of Harman’s ontology. Against any contextualist reading of this idea he tells us that objects exist in a temporal movement in which they are “plugged into certain limited systems of machinery while excluded from others”, so that every object “exerts a determinate and limited range of effects in each instant, and is equally determined by the equipment that surrounds it” (TB, p. 10). This “totality of equipment” which a later reading might call an assemblage means that each object “occupies a thoroughly specific position in the system of forces that makes up the world” (TB, p. 10). This vast assemblage of objects is the world. What this implicates is the central motif of his ontology that the world of objects “is an invisible realm from which the visible infrastructure of the universe emerges” (TB, p. 11).
The unitary effect of all objects in collusion (i.e., your SR blog object as object-effect) is part of what he terms the equipment as unitary effect:
The tool-being of the ready-to-hand is not simply withdrawn from view “for the most part,” since it is irreducible by definition to anything that could ever be seen. From now on, I will use the phrases “equipment,” “the ready-to-hand,” and “tool-being” to refer exclusively to the level of their subterranean reality, which never comes openly to view. … Thus, in this sense, equipment is invisible. And at this stage, tools also cannot be regarded as discrete natural units that would enter into systems only accidentally, as if they were independent solids retaining their integrity in the face of the wildest combinations. Equipment is a unitary effect, its various tool-pieces absorbed into the Imperium of function that it inaugurates, each of them separable from it only by way of abstraction or outright physical removal. Equipment is total. (Tool-being, pp. 11-12)
It’s this idea of absorption into the larger assemblage of this function which is the SR Blog which is the unitary effect of this function or structure he calls the ‘totality of equipment’. In this case the SR blog object-effect…
March 2, 2011 at 9:32 pm
Thanks Alex,
I wish I had better answers to your questions but I think these are some of the hardest things to work through. My intuition is that time is not a medium in which objects move, but is rather something produced by objects themselves. I think there’s a lot of compelling evidence for this both from phenomenology, but also coming out of cognitive and neuroscience, as well as animal ethology. If this is the case, time would have to be theorized in a variety of ways depending on the object being investigated. Each type of object would temporalize the world differently. The temporality of a dragon fly would differ from that of a human, and the time of a social system would differ yet again. These temporalities would play a key role in how objects are able to relate to one another. Temporality would be particularly significant in defining the limits and conditions under which a particular type of entity can be perturbed by other events. Thus, for example, certain events are unable to perturb us as humans because they move either too fast or too slow with respect to our spatio-temporal schemata.
I suspect that there are two additional senses of time. In addition to the manner in which an object temporalizes its world, there would also be the time of the object. This would be the rate at which it produces its events or its components… Roughly what counts as an “instant” or a moment for an object. In rhetoric, for example, this might be the minimal rate at which a communication event can be produced. This sort of temporality would differ for a-semiotic machines such as bank computer banks or the computers behind the stock market, and for human beings engaged in communication with one another. The really difficult problems begin to emerge with the third type of time which would consist of emergent temporalities pertaining to objects related to one another. I’m still thinking through all of this.
March 3, 2011 at 1:02 am
Your discussion on blog-objects got me thinking about other odd objects like the previous discussions on fictional characters. Fictional objects are historical in the same sense in that an object like Popeye is able to ‘expand’ and transform himself by translations with other mediums/objects (a Popeye t-shirt, Popeye video, etc) while simultaneously replaying the Popeye history (fictional and non-fictional time-line) so as to breed further Popeye objects. In other words, the Popeye lifeline is set on repeat but each repetition produces something new (more Popeye-like objects).
March 3, 2011 at 1:58 am
Levi, here’s the claim that raises my eyebrows, and I suspect it’s the same thing Michael at ARCHIVE FIRE was concerned about:
“When events take place in the world outside of the SR-blog-object, these events can perturb that object in a variety of ways, but the information that the SR-blog-object produces as a result of these perturbations will not be a function of the external events themselves, but of the internal organization of the SR-blog-object”.
Right: It’s not WHOLLY a function of the “external events themselves”, but neither is it WHOLLY a function of the “internal organization of the object”. It’s a function of BOTH, and the feedback obtained only by their interaction. So, I can see no way to correctly say that they never “touch” each other.
Here’s a good example (relevant to your quest for more physical activity :) Laura Bell writes in the Jan29 SCIENCE NEWS about “Making Nuanced Memories: Nerve cells help the brain tell similar experiences apart” – by exercising “pattern separation”. Bell cites Henritte van Praag of the Neuroplasticity & Behavioral Unit at the National Institute on Aging: “Exercise is the strongest neurgenic stimulus”, adding that “While exercise encourages new nerve cells, a healthy diet may help keep more of the cells”. In both cases, the internal organization can’t do it without the external stimulus. Your internal organization would be very different if you were locked up in a cage with no access to healthy food or exercise.
Obviously you know this! It’s just the claims that sound like U1 + Y = U2 as solely a FUNCTION of U that provoke disagreement.
March 3, 2011 at 2:15 am
Hey Mark,
I think it’s important to preserve those instances where an acting object produces it’s own events. Otherwise objects would be purely passive. In my view operations can take place within objects that are purely a product of the dynamism of the object. I think this is Kant’s singular contribution (the one that gets Deleuze all excited). In the second and third critique, Kant conceives a mode of self-production that isn’t merely an entity being activated by an external stimuli. This was the inspiration of both his moral law (divorced from all “pathological” motivation) and his aesthetic insights. The bizarre thing about a “synthetic a priori” judgment is that it is something that arises entirely from an agent yet creates something new. This, I think, is what needs to be preserved in a theory of auto/allo-poietic objects… This “a priori” creativity.
March 3, 2011 at 10:58 am
Hi Levi,
Long time (albeit inconsistent) lurker, first off thanks for blogging so prolifically and fascinatingly.
I would like to take up your response to Mark’s post if I could, and push you a little further on this idea of “a priori” creativity with respect to your onticology. You stated early on in this post that there are only objects, properties and relations in your framework, are you rendering the synthetic a priori as a property of objects? And if so, is there a danger of smuggling in a final “psyche” possessing unit here?
Or perhaps more correctly, is the distinction between external events and internal dynamics relative to the size or scale of the objects that you are looking at? An event produced internally at the level of the SR-blog-object, is the agglomeration of the interactions between the blogs composing this larger object with other blogs (and further objects) external to themselves, and so on and so forth – blogs all the way down. Which seems to me to be consistent with a lack of primordial units.
March 3, 2011 at 11:23 am
Added an essay in response, Levi…
http://earth-wizard.livejournal.com/75584.html
March 3, 2011 at 11:59 am
Dear Levi,
More and more it seems that everything you write resonates within me and enters into relation with my own writing and my PhD research on complex ecologies of live art. Most of what you write here is in agreement with my own thought, let’s say my thought resonates in sympathy with yours and that is definitely what I imagine Spinoza meant when he wrote about laetitia or joy.
However I have been trying to approach what I see is a problem in Luhmann’s conception of the operational closure of systems. If I understand it properly, Luhmann (and Varela and most second-order systems theory) define systems as entities totally closed to the environment that reproduce themselves with or without the production of novelty (according to Luhmann or Varela, respectively) but always as a result of their own operation, that is, without transference of information from the environment into the system. This seems to be related to the fact that the system won’t ever be able to grasp its environment but only to create what varela calls the “world,” that is an idea of alterity that is dialectically enacted by the system as a byproduct of its own meachanisms of production of selfhood.
Now the fact that the contemporary world is seeing an increasing complex
March 3, 2011 at 12:07 pm
Now the fact the the contemporary environment is suffering an increasing complexification due to the proliferation of technology makes me wonder if indeed the system can simply ignore the complexification of the environment and reduce it through selection. In the particular case of art objects I wonder if the environment (and in this particular case the institutional, cultural, economic, etc., environment) won’t be actually acting or directly influencing the production of sense in the experience of art. Will it be possible, you think, that given our increasing dependence on an ever-more complex and technological environment, that our own agency and the way we enter in relation with other objects and allow ourselves to affect and be affected by them is actually an agency we share (however provisionally and contingently) with the environment which we and the objects we relate to inhabit? Will it be possible that we are indeed cyborgs in Haraway’s sense, i.e. system-environment hybrids?
Does this make any sense?
March 3, 2011 at 12:10 pm
P.S. – Can the environment be part of us as a monstrous Leviathan in the sense Latour gives it?
Thanks for reading this and for your inspiring thought.
March 3, 2011 at 6:45 pm
Mark Crosby hits it squarely on the head when he writes:
“It’s not WHOLLY a function of the ‘external events themselves’, but neither is it WHOLLY a function of the ‘internal organization of the object’. It’s a function of BOTH, and the feedback obtained only by their interaction. So, I can see no way to correctly say that they never ‘touch’ each other.”
I can think of no way that someone can adequately argue that “external events” and “internal organization” do not interact directly. I accept a formal closure based on the functional thresholding or affective governing powers of a system/object, but I would also argue that the immanent character of cosmological properties (it’s materiality if you will) affords a unified (“flat”) plane of reality within which it is possible for objects to directly (but never fully) interact and affect each other. This is what I mean when I say that there is an ontological intimacy between or among objects which makes them vulnerable to modification, mutation, destruction, hybridity. Perhaps this is the monsterous quality of things – the horror that not only Kurtz witnessed by from which we ourselves often recoil?
March 3, 2011 at 9:43 pm
[…] when Mark Crosby commented with this; “It’s not WHOLLY a function of the ‘external events […]
March 7, 2011 at 3:04 am
“So, I can see no way to correctly say that they never ‘touch’ each other.”
This seems to be the biggest stumbling block for many, but it’s really not a complicated mystery. They touch, but only indirectly as their reality is being siphoned off into a larger system. Even if an object is crushing another or contemplating it passively, it can’t help but be caught up into an emergent object which is reducing both (interior) objects’ powers or realities. The idea is that the two objects don’t encounter each other “as such,” floating in a vacuum, but rather in the context of another system (call that system relation, perception, causation — it simply reverts back to the OOO definition of object, which is what it was all along: an emergent causality which is less than the sum of its pieces — hat tip to Robert Jackson, I believe, who used that particular phrase). It does not mean objects are invulnerable, eternal, unchangeable or indivisible, simply that the circuit of causation isn’t a disembodied one between two things (direct) but a compromise which yields a third thing (indirect, vicarious). It’s really one of the most elegantly simple and cogent aspects of object-oriented ontology.
March 8, 2011 at 3:03 am
Joseph: Thanks. Your comment helps. I do agree that two “real objects” only “touch” by virtue of a third. However, I don’t think that this is necessarily a “siphoning” or a reduction.
Robert: I did perhaps “miss the point” in that Levi was talking about social objects (the “blog object”) while my example was a bit different. When a person is inspired to get more exercise, what are the objects involved? I don’t think this decision (to get more exercise) is solely a decision on the person’s part. I read that exercise stimulates certain neural growth that helps maintains intelligence as one ages, and decide to get more exercise. As Levi aptly noticed, this is an “instance where an acting object produces its own event”.
My point is that the “acting object” cannot do this on its own. First, it develops this desire over the course of many interactions. Second, it requires an environment in which enhanced exercise can occur. Still, if I go out running, what is the “object” I’m interacting with? Is the path I take and the slopes I climb an “object”? Obviously this is not “reciprocal” feedback; nevertheless, there are many influences from outside that directly or indirectly contribute to both my decision to get more exercise and the resulting growth of neural capacity that results.
I just find talk of “objects”, in this example, to be somewhat simplistic (which is similar to the way I feel about your Jan25 “Code and the Non-Ubiquity of Emergence” claim that “nothing is generated” by an algorithm that “simply counts” ; )
March 11, 2011 at 5:24 pm
[…] that distort the other object being related to in some way or another. In a very similar vein, I have argued, drawing heavily on Luhmann’s sociological autopoietic systems theory and cybernetics, that […]
March 30, 2011 at 5:23 pm
[…] me terminó resultando mucho más claro cuando leí este artículo de Levy Bryant con precisiones respecto a su entendimiento de lo que son o cómo oper…. En resumen, la manera como todo objeto exhibe comportamiento de sistema, compuesto a su vez por […]