I already began to develop this thesis somewhat in an earlier post yet didn’t completely drive it home. Some people seem to think that the function of philosophy is to rigorously ground claims so as to get at The Truth(tm). As an empiricist that values actual concrete empirical research whether it be the political activist engaged in affecting the social assemblage in which they’re entangled, the artist experimenting with a new style, the ethnographer or sociologist investigating a social assemblage, the person in the humanities plumbing the archives, the engineer working at the invention of a new technology, or the biologist, physicist, or chemist doing laboratory work. Indeed, I’m even fascinated in the young person exploring the affects produced in a rave or a rock band, or two lovers inventing a new form of singular relation between one another. These are all empiricisms in their own fashion. They’re all explorations of the wilderness of being.
For me philosophy is a parasitic discipline that is without an object beyond the Present of its historical moment. It is beyond truth or falsehood in the referential sense, instead striving to think the sense of its Time. With Badiou I thus hold that Truths always come from elsewhere, outside of philosophy, from politics, art, love, and science. Philosophy has no Truths of its own and is thus a sort of empty square that travels an aleatory course throughout history. In this regard, there are no “questions of philosophy” that could be summed up in a textbook for all time. The questions of philosophy will always be a function of its Time or the eternity of its Present. Nonetheless, philosophy strives to think that which is singularly eternal and concretely universal in its Time or the Present. With Deleuze and Guattari, I thus hold that philosophy is a creation of concepts. As they write in What is Philosophy?, “…philosophy is the art of forming, inventing, and fabricating concepts” (2). Concepts do not fall ready made and fully formed from the sky, rather they must be built.
Concepts are not representations, nor are they ideas in minds. Rather, they are lenses and tools. They are apparatuses, every bit as tangible and real as hammers. It makes as much sense to ask “is this concept true?” as it does to ask “is a hammer true?” Drawing a concept from Ryle, this question constitutes a category mistake. And it is a category mistake that constitutes some of the most tiresome and fascistically terrifying attitudes in all of philosophy. Everywhere with this question of whether a concept is true, whether it represents the world, we encounter the desire to police, dominate, subordinate, and render subservient. Like Kafka’s Court or Castle, these philosophical technologies everywhere seek to trap, ensnare, halt, and limit. They create the illusion of free movement and autonomy, while everywhere weaving a semantic web about engagement seeking to fix it. The question “is it true?” is the insecure and narcissitic fantasy of academic philosophy wishing to redeem itself by functioning as master discipline, legislator, and judge of all other disciplines, practices, and experiences. The artist, physicist, ethnographer, and activist get along just fine without this type of “philosopher” to examine their papers. The proper questions when encountering a hammer is not “is it true?”, but rather “what does it do?”, “what can I do with it?”, “is it put together well for these tasks?”, and so on.
Read on!
William James somewhere famously speaks of the buzzing, blooming confusion of experience. Being is a jumble that in and of itself provides no vectors of its joints. Concepts are lenses and apparatuses. The question to ask a concept is not “is it true?” but is closer to the sorts of questions we ask of a microscope, radio telescope, or hammer. Nothing in the world tells me what to attend to or what to see. The question to ask of a concept is “what does it allow me to see?”, “what risks does it involve?”, “what does it allow me to do?”, “what affective attitudes and personae or human types does it generate?”, “what social relations or new forms social collective does it create?”, “what practices does it invite?”, “what affective attitudes towards other persons and nonhumans does it produce?”, “what hierarchies does it embody?”, “what new paths of invention, practice, research and invention does it breech?”, and so on. Concepts are meant to work and only live in working. They aren’t meant to represent.
So many philosophers seem to desire to legislate and judge, rather than listen and hear. At any point in history the world is populated by Truths, yet Truths have the peculiar property of not being reflexive. In the domains of art, love, science, and politics they are haphazardly lived and enacted while, as it were, remaining unconscious. Philosophy strives to bring a little reflexivity to the Present. It strives to grasp that which is concretely universal and singularly eternal in the Present (Truths) so that these Truths might appear a little more intensively in the world, a little more legibly, and so that these Truths might become capable of enjoying new aleatory adventures and inventions in the order of Time. Concepts are performative or enactive, not representational.
The other day Mel told me a story about her students in one of her English classes. They said that they had never heard of structural patriarchy. They had sensed a number of things were wrong in the world and in their lives, yet had experienced these things as either being the way of the world or a fault of their own or the people they are involved with. Structural patriarchy is a concept, and as a concept it selects something from chaos or the buzzing confusion of experience, and functions as both a lens and a tool calling for us to attend to certain relevancies or significant points in the world. With this sad concept the possibility of affirmation follows. The students are now able to stitch together a series of seemingly disparate phenomena in their social world, to recognize their contingency and injustice, and to begin devising strategies to transform them. Atwood’s Handmaiden’s Tale is now, for them, no longer a harrowing science fiction story about a terrible universe involving the travails of this particular woman, but is instead an exploration of the tendencies active in our world. The eternity of the singular jumps into relief. This concept both grasps something of its historical present, but also points the way to a set of practices for changing it. The Truth of the concept is not that our present is defined by structural patriarchy, but rather the egalitarian practices that emerge from this naming allowing another future to become available. There, before the concept, was yearning for something else and suffering, yet in inchoate form. With the concept, this yearning and suffering take on determinate form allowing for the emergence of practices and invention. Concepts are precious things and do not fall from the sky ready made. The only relevant question when they do appear is whether something can be done with them and whether the practices they invite are worthwhile.
June 2, 2011 at 6:14 am
And as Badiou insists it is our fidelity to those truths that allows them to endure and create. Perhaps this is something forgotten in the search for a master: the unity of theory & practice – thus covering that blooming buzzing confusion with their layer of dust. No wonder their ideas fail to animate us. You remind us here that philosophy can and should be a gaya scienza.
June 2, 2011 at 12:47 pm
as a neoish-pragmatist I can relate to all of this except “Nonetheless, philosophy strives to think that which is singularly eternal and concretely universal in its Time or the Present.” seems like a slight hangover of the epochal/structuralist daze of old, why speak of “universal” or “its Time”?
that said yes to gay sciences!
June 2, 2011 at 2:00 pm
Here is where Rorty reading Davidson on metaphors reminds me of JeffBell/Stengers (and “Man Thinking” by Gregg Lambert in the Other Emerson), I think this offers a bridge between the Continental and ordinary language philosophies on the status of concepts/metaphors as not being “different” worlds (http://www.torilmoi.com/wp-content/uploads/2009/09/Moi_They-Practice-Their-Trades.pdf)but in terms of the relationship between Gay and normal sciences.
http://books.google.com/books?id=UCwX_UIu9nEC&pg=PA14&lpg=PA14&dq=rorty+davidson+metaphor&source=bl&ots=FCS3KjrmlG&sig=PNFxswL1KRG7pSaKCEX9iUKxih4&hl=en&ei=LL62TcPRGcactwe71rF8&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=7&ved=0CEoQ6AEwBg#v=onepage&q&f=false
June 2, 2011 at 3:47 pm
I’m speechless Levi.
I honestly couldn’t agree more with you in this post. Truly. I never realized you were so pragmatic.
I like to try to think through the links one might forge between an anthropological appreciation of human adaptivity and tool use, Tim Ingold’s work on wayfinding, Heidegger’s ideas about primordial care and coping, Habermas’ developmental competencies, and the pragmatists. The thread running through all of these narratives is, in my opinion, adaptivity, or affective plasticity as a coping and embodied intentionality. Adaptivity (in both an active and passive sense) is a fundamental feature of the way certain beings exist in the world.
The reason why I bring this up is because I’m still reeling from discovering in your last post that you and I have unwittingly arrived at the same place: http://www.archivefire.net/2010/08/i-got-love.html
Your evocation of the trope of ‘the wilderness of being’ is alarming to me since this has been the most important notion in the whole of my intellectual life for about 5 years now. In fact it has been so important to my worldview that I have only ever mentioned it once (see the link above) for fear of letting the ‘sacred’ power of its resonances seep out into the general public. But here you are nailing in the wall and giving offering it up for all the world to see.
June 2, 2011 at 5:35 pm
[…] current post is something of a […]
June 2, 2011 at 9:45 pm
I was a voracious undergraduate philosophy student, and always felt like a nomad in a laboratory when it came to thinking like a philosopher.
The scrutiny philosophers undertake in looking for Truth results from their feeling that everyone else has just arrived in their zone of the laboratory during a mania.
I like Zizek’s quip that the First Task of philosophy is to show people what deep shit we’re in.
I suggest in passing that Franz Rosenzweig is a philosopher you should all be consulting regarding the Present, Eternity, a new thinking, concepts as paths and courses. Readers of Deleuze & Guattari will recognize the most tremendous artistry and precision in Rosenzweig’s The Star of Redemption.
read on…
June 3, 2011 at 12:28 am
If concepts are supposed to take on determinate forms, thereby allowing for emergence of practices, the are they not inching towards ideologies in the Zizekian sense?
June 3, 2011 at 5:52 am
>The question to ask of a concept is “what does >it allow me to see?”, “what risks does it >involve?”, “what does it allow me to do?”, >“what affective attitudes and personae or human >types does it generate?”, “what social >relations or new forms social collective does >it create?”, “what practices does it invite?”, >“what affective attitudes towards other persons >and nonhumans does it produce?”, “what >hierarchies does it embody?”, “what new paths >of invention, practice, research and invention >does it breech?”, and so on. Concepts are meant >to work and only live in working. They aren’t >meant to represent.
I can’t say that I’m particular interested in answering any of these questions, no less formulating them for myself. If they arise as secondary considerations, so be it, but the day utility and/or productivity takes priority for thinking is the day I throw myself under a train. Not that I object to the general refutation of Kantian legislature, but if I find solace in philosophy it is precisely in as much as it divests me of the demands of productivity, of positive contribution to society, collectivity, whatever those are.
June 3, 2011 at 8:43 am
As I understand it, concepts are not true just because they’re not candidates for truth.
Sentences like “Concepts are not representations, nor are they ideas in minds. Rather, they are lenses and tools.”
are candidates for truth/falsity because they are used to make assertions.
(I realize that this response makes me sound like one of Harman’s epistemological plods, or a pedant.)
June 3, 2011 at 2:26 pm
[…] the light of Levi Bryant’s claim that concepts are not ‘true’ in his post ‘The Function of Philosophy’ – one reiterated by Graham Harman here. Here’s […]
June 4, 2011 at 12:58 am
There is a part of me that wants to echo Benoît and a part of me that wants to say that the complaint he raises is somewhat short-sighted.
I agree, basically, that “the day utility and/or productivity takes priority for thinking is the day I throw myself under a train.” But in my eyes, this has happened, and is basically the norm with academic philosophy. And this is what Levi and others here are rejecting, I think. For isn’t the submission to “Truth” (in a way that could be controlled by the ‘epistemological police’) enslave, ahem, truth to “Truth”? Isn’t this the greatest putting-to-use of concepts and representations that there could be?
Thus, while I have argued (often on this blog) against the tool-aspect or utility-aspect of (OOO, etc.) philosophy, I think a more measured approach needs to be taken here. Levi writes “as a tool or a lens.” When a five-year-old uses a magnifying glass to examine (or to sizzle) a moth taking a rest on his driveway, is he putting the lens “to use” in the way that we would ‘philosophically’ object to submitting objects to ‘use’? Or is he opening himself to the mysteriousness of his world, investigating it, thinking about himself and his body in relation to other worlds and other bodies? I think the latter. So sure, a tool may be in operation in a way that subjugates people from their labor time, constructs a hideous monstrosity and levels a forest. But you can also build a tree-house with a hammer. Or, why not, a home.
Alas, I have a great affinity for those writers/philosophers who emphasize this notion of unworking or non-working (from Kant’s idea of purposeless purpose, through Nietzsche’s rigorous truth-testings, reaching to Bataille (unemployed negativity), Blanchot (desoeuvrement), Nancy (inoperativity), etc). For Bataille especially, this was crucial: language itself, in all its guises, is too often put under the yoke of industry, of consumerism, of egotism, of ideology, etc. For him, the prime goal of any writing/thought was to “insubordinate” language, to undermine the claim to language as a “tool.” Here we have Heidegger contrasting the instrumental use of language with the opening-to-poetic-language, such that the thought or being of Being was disclosed or made-way-for. We have Paul Celan writing that we must cease thinking of man as instrument, and instead think of man as silence– and that only in this way do we begin writing, thinking, communicating, etc. (I’m paraphrasing of course).
But I think we have to read between the lines here and not just take the words at ‘face value’ (for isn’t this also an implicit assumption, that all words can do is be explicit and transparent, can only be used as operators, etc). If not to uncover the “true intention,” we must at least try to gauge what kind of lens or tool we are offered. Chances are, if it is offered, freely, for all to see and to engage, less than impose itself on us, it exposes us. Personally, “to expose ourselves at the limit of ourselves”– this is a ‘purpose’ for which the aforementioned writers fought, and put their words ‘to use’ toward that end.
To me, Levi’s statement or view of the ‘uses’ of concepts doesn’t explicitly or implicitly seek to put the truth to work. If anything, the very opposite: it is to recognize the contingency of our truths, of truth as a process, to put concepts in line with a becoming which affirms “rescindivity.” With tool/lens, we can build and deconstruct. An abstract machine, an event like a text like this, which ‘operates’ or ‘works on’ on my consciousness as I read it– it is a whole zone of “de-” and “re-territorializations.”
In short, just because someone uses the metaphors or analogs of ‘work’ doesn’t mean that they are trying to subjugate their thought to some ulterior motive, some productive goal to be seamlessly subsumed in the mindless flux of industrial ideologies. It doesn’t mean they are one and the same with the blind productive mechanisms. And one can use these words, as I think they are used here, against “use,” even when advocating it. And when it comes to poetry, isn’t any word up for grabs, open to play, there to be used, abused, refused, disabused, disused..?
June 4, 2011 at 1:09 am
Another, “in short”… In short, it’s always good to remember the Wittgensteinian caution to take a look at how we use words in an every-day setting, and not to restrict our philosophical discourse by thinking that words have to mean something totally different there than they do in our discourse.
We use words. That doesn’t have to mean that we put them to use. Personally, for a writer like myself, this is the perennial problem, question, challenge when it comes to navigating silence and words. (Hopefully I’ve justified my lengthy and multiple comments here with this last admission).
June 4, 2011 at 3:30 am
“Nothing in the world tells me what to attend to or what to see” — is this true?
“So many philosophers seem to desire to legislate and judge, rather than listen and hear.” — Philosophers 0, Levi 1
June 4, 2011 at 5:00 am
Not to forget: “philo-sophy” means not the practicality or the certainty, but the love of wisdom. Put the accent on love and wisdom starts to be produced and circulated in a very interesting way.
June 5, 2011 at 12:02 am
1. LarvalSubjects, this sentence does not go anywhere. I demand to know where it was going.
2. Also, I don’t know how many philosophers ask the question of whether or not a concept in and of itself is true. The questions associated with a concept are more likely to be: “Is this concept applicable?”, “Does this concept adequately describe part or all of the phenomenon to which it is being applied?”, and “Is this concept which I am applying to an object incompatible with another concept which I am applying to that same object?”
3. Truth-claims have a place. They are used to judge the legitimacy of propositions. Whether your theory of truth is based on logical coherence or on real correspondence, the question of whether something is true or not is important.
June 5, 2011 at 5:43 am
I was actually expecting, given this blog’s deep involvement in/cofounding of OOO, that this post would turn in a somewhat different direction… As I understand it, OOO’s insight about hammers is that they aren’t just tools–that they also perceive and misperceive, use and misuse the human beings who fashioned them, in ways those human beings could not have predicted. Pragmatism is fine and good, but what’s more interesting to me is a situation where humans DON’T have sovereign control over concepts in the same way we don’t have that control over hammers. So, how might a concept exceed and overpower the pragmatic/instrumental intent of its owner, hmm? :)
June 5, 2011 at 5:44 am
*by owner I meant “creator,” sry
June 5, 2011 at 5:48 am
*but I guess also “owner” in the sense of each “user” of the concept, though possibly having differential effects between users & over time… maybe this was the “unthought” of my first post? hehe
June 10, 2011 at 7:27 pm
It is true that concepts in themselves can be judged neither true nor false, unless it contains a logical inconsistency. But I wonder, if you are not using your useful concepts to produce true statements about the world, then what are you using them for?
June 11, 2011 at 12:52 am
[…] a number of people seemed to have a problem with my discussion of concepts in my post entitled On the Function of Philosophy. There, I wrote, Concepts are not representations, nor are they ideas in minds. Rather, they are […]
November 24, 2011 at 8:16 pm
Keep on philosophizing