As I teach Morton’s The Ecological Thought this semester, I find myself thinking a lot about ecological ethics and politics. I really think we’re only barely able to pose these questions at this point. Part of the problem lies at the level of the very connotations of language, perpetually getting in the way of what needs to be thought. In a lot of ways this is what Tim is trying to address in his critique of what I call the “spatial or geographical concept of nature” is a critique of this issue. If I understand Morton correctly, what he’s critiquing in works like Ecology Without Nature and The Ecological Thought is a geographical or spatial concept of nature. On the one hand, there is the domain of the city, the suburbs, the town, and the farm that is the world of society; while on the other hand there is the domain of the great barrier reefs, Brazilian rain forests, and Utah Badlands outside of society. Under this model, nature is a place that you go to outside of the city and suburbs. It’s a geography. From an ecological perspective, this is problematic because it places ecological concerns pretty low on the hierarchy of concerns. Are you going to worry about things like economic injustice, racism, sexism, homophobia, etc. (the city) or the great spotted owl? Worrying about the great spotted owl seems like the worry of the privileged and the decadent because antagonisms revolving around the economic, racism, sexism, homophobia, etc., are more directly relevant to our social world or geographical locality.
Morton’s proposal– notorious among some environmental activists –is that we abandon the concept of nature. Now, I’m with the environmentalists in being bothered by the idea of abandoning the concept of nature, but I think for different reasons. In other words, I think they’re missing his point. Morton’s point, it seems to me, is not that we should abandon the concept of nature so as to no longer worry about the great spotted owl, but that where we conceive of nature as something outside society, we also end up treating things like the demise of the spotted owl as being of no social concern. My reason for being reticent to abandon the concept of nature are different from those of the environmentalist. First, I understand nature in a different way than Morton. For me “nature” does not signify a place outside of society, but rather is a synonym for being or existence, signifying the totality of what exists, composed entirely of physical or material beings, interacting through causes. In other words, for me minds and society are no less a part of nature than society. This is a part of my general polemic against idealism, Platonism, theistic religions, etc. There are only physical causes in my ontology and I think there are a number of reasons that it’s important to emphasize this. I’m not sure that Morton would disagree with this, though I have been troubled by his polemics against materialism as I think materialism, far from leading to an “enframing” of the world, instead leads us to appreciate the bodily, affective, and fragility of things, as well as the work and energy that go into everything (I think the expenditure of energy is one of the great oversights of how power and control functions in critical theory).
read on!
I also worry that since, at the semiotic level, concepts are organized around binary oppositions, abandoning the concept of nature ineluctably leads us into a pan-culturalism (a variant of idealism) anathema to Morton’s intentions. In other words, if we take thinkers such as Derrida and Lacan seriously– as we should –we should never have faith in the power of the content of how our arguments function, but also need to attend to the anonymous play of language in the linguistic field and how, as Lacan puts it somewhere in Seminar 5, language “cuckolds” us, using it for our own ends despite our best intentions. If, diacritically or oppositionally, the term “nature” immediately evokes the term “culture”, then erasure of nature risks turning everything into culture. I don’t think this is Morton’s intention, but that’s how language functions. It is on the grounds of how linguistic fields function that I come down hard on Morton in Onto-Cartography, not on the grounds of his intentions. With Althusser– under Montag’s reading –we need to intend to the effects of our discourse, rather than privileging the intentions of our discourse, as our writings are material entities interacting casually with brains and the social world like anything else. As an aside, it should be pointed out that the withdrawal thesis of object-oriented philosophy, which is not synonymous with object-oriented ontology, tends towards this sort of intentionalism (is it a surprise that we’ve seen a return to certain discourses of genius in creative production in some strains of this thought?). For this reason, given the choice, while fully endorsing Morton’s rejection of the spatial concept of nature, I nonetheless think that pan-naturalism is the way to go. We must find it in ourselves to see even society and history as a part of nature. This, I suppose, is my lineage from Lucretius and Spinoza; the two philosophers to whom I claim greatest allegiance when I’m being honest.
I digress. In seeking to de-suture nature and ecology, I think Morton is proposing an ecological ontology. Where ordinarily we take “ecology” to signify the study or investigation of natural ecosystems, Morton’s thesis at this period in his work is that being is ecological through and through. In other words, “nature” is not the distinctive feature of ecology, but rather ecology is the investigation of how things relate, interact, and depend on one another, and every being, whether cultural or “natural”, is ecological through and through. Put differently, there is no being independent of relation. To think ecologically is therefore to think beings in terms of their relations and interactions with other entities. As Morton remarks in the first chapter (in paraphrase), being is a Saussurean system, composed of relations or differences without positive terms. While there are plenty of reasons to question this thesis as us object-oriented ontologists have pointed out– and I’m increasingly reluctant to classify myself with that term –nonetheless, it’s difficult to argue that beings aren’t perpetually in some sort of relation even if they don’t also always have a minimal ontological excess over those relations that allows them to migrate into other relations. For me, what’s interesting and important is not entities isolated or withdrawn from relations, but what happens when entities encounter new entities and thereby forge new relations.
What we get here is a logic of the “and” rather than the “or”. In a non-ecological ontology, we either 1) see the qualities of a being as arising from within that being independent of all other beings (e.g. genes defining the features of the phenotype), or 2) trace effects or qualities back to a single cause. In a mesh or ecology this no longer holds as it’s a variety of causes that produce effects. For example, the sex of a fetus is a product of the genes and diet and hormones and birth order and probably other things besides. It is the result of an interplay between all of these things, not one of these things. The color of my coffee mug is ecological in this sense. It’s not in the mug, but is the result of an interplay between wavelengths of light, nervous systems, and the chemical properties of the mug. When we turn out the lights, it’s not that the mug remains blue and we just can’t see it, it’s that the blog has genuinely lost it’s color because it’s not interacting with other bodies such as photons of light.
Maybe what I mean when I say that we’ve barely begun to think the implications of ecology for ethics now becomes clear in light of the foregoing. When we hear the term “ecological ethics”, our first thought (or my first thought) is to think that this is a special domain of ethics devoted to how we should comport ourselves to nature. How ought we treat the spotted owl? What we here need to remember– a point the Brandomians and Sellarsians in their neo-Kantianism haven’t quite grasped yet –is that every ethics is based on an ontology. If it is true that being itself is ecological and that ecology isn’t just a special domain of ethics, then this raises a number of questions for how we think about ethics (questions to which I do not have answers). Much of our contemporary ethical thought is based on ideas of responsibility, and assigning praise and blame. This presupposes a theory of causation that can be traced back to a single origin in an actor. But if it is true that every property is an event produced through an interaction of interactants, then it is no longer possible to talk about causality in these terms. Every cause is an effect and every effect is a cause without us being able to decide what caused what.
I encourage anyone reading this to think about these questions very concretely, not like academics talking about Derrida, Badiou, or Levinas in abstractions, but in terms of men like Ariel Castro that abducted women and made them sex slaves for ten years. Practice good phenomenology and return to life and real circumstances. Stay close to the ethical issues you deal with in your own lives and dealings with the world. What are we to do with cases like the Ariel Castros of the world in an ecological ontology– which is probably right –that refuses to trace everything back to a causal origin but instead sees every individual as an interactant. I do not intend this as a low blow to ecological ontology as this is the direction I myself am moving in, but am instead asking how we handle instances like this where we clear wish– or I do anyway –wish to assign responsibility and culpability (Bennett raises similar issues in Vibrant Matter). What we need, I think, is a conceptual framework that’s rich enough to deal with interactivism while nonetheless preserving our ability to adjudicate these ethical issues. I’m not at all sure where even to begin.
September 13, 2013 at 8:41 pm
I think theories of coalition, largely developed within feminist and queer movements, can be applied to ecological thought as a way of approaching ethical and political questions. By thinking about how diverse and imbricated material formations act in concert to produce effects, in differential fashions, we can think about power and ethics without relying on linear causality. Judith Butler’s recent text on the occupy movement does some of this work I think: http://www.eipcp.net/transversal/1011/butler/en
September 13, 2013 at 9:19 pm
Ian,
How do you see these collective formations as related to ethics? I’m not sure I understand. Presumably when we talk about ethics we’re raising questions about the good life, praise and blame, duties, etc. All of these concepts presuppose a certain ontology of individuals and the world. If we find out that being is quite different than what we thought, this calls for revision of these concepts and even abandonment in some cases. How are we to think of Castro’s culpability– if at all — in a universe that is ecological and where we thus can’t clearly sort causes?
September 13, 2013 at 9:49 pm
I think we can locate ethics in ecologies in two ways.
The first borrows from spinoza (and also epicurus), in which the ‘good life’ is always seen as relation, in-between, entangled, imbricated, and about producing a balance of forces with this in mind. For Spinoza, in Book IV of Ethics, we read:
“Proof. – The human body needs many other bodies for its preservation. But that which constitutes the specific reality (forma) of a human body is, that its parts communicate their several motions one to another in a certain fixed proportion. Therefore, whatsoever brings about the preservation of the proportion between motion and rest, which the parts of the human body mutually possess, preserves the specific reality of the human body and consequently renders the human body capable of being affected in many ways and of affecting external bodies in many ways; consequently it is good
XXVII. The advantage which we derive from things external to us, besides the experience and knowledge which we acquire from observing them, and from recombining their elements in different forms, is principally the preservation of the body; from this point of view, those things are most useful which can so feed and nourish the body, that all its parts may rightly fulfill their functions. For, in proportion as the body is capable of being affected in a greater variety of ways, and of affecting external bodies in a great number of ways, so much the more is the mind capable of thinking.”
This assertion that living things are always-already dependent on other bodies (broadly understood as not just human bodies, but rather material “bodies” of all kinds) for their well being allows us to produce an ethics through which we could look at ecosystems, their flows, cycles, etc., and place values on certain kinds of reproductive processes that ensure the health of that system (an the different formations that circulate within it). This almost comes to resemble a cybernetics ethics. Someone like Castro, and the ecological/social forces that produced and act in concert with him, could be seen as interrupting these chains of care and reproduction, and these assemblages and flows could be blocked on ethical grounds.
The second grounds upon which we could talk about an ecological ethics would be borrowing more from Deleuze. I think this passage from Elizabeth Grosz forces us to approach these questions of ecological ethics quite well:
“Feminism … is not simply the struggle to liberate women, even though it has tended to conceive of itself in these terms (if this is its function, it has failed miserably!): it is the struggle to render more mobile, fluid and transformable the means by which the female subject is produced and represented. It is the struggle to produce a future in which forces align in ways fundamentally different from the past and the present. This struggle is not a struggle by subjects to be recognized and valued, to be and to be seen to be what they are, but a struggle to mobilize and transform the position of women, the alignment of forces that constitute that ‘identity’ and ‘position’, that stratification that stabilizes itself as a place and an identity. Politics can be seen as the struggle of imperceptible forces, forces in us and around, forces in continual conflict; it is a useful fiction to imagine that we as subjects are masters or agents of these very forces that constitute us as subjects, but misleading.”
This is a coalitional “way out” of forcing our ethics to be solely about the culpability/responsibility of the individual, and instead allows us to think ethically about society/ecology as systems in ethical ways. Again, in the case of Castro, the question of what to do with him specifically would be less of an ethical concern (although we could come to conclusions about this when considering what a healthy ecology should be in this present moment), but instead we look to what confluence of forces and flows produced and gave duration to someone like Castro, and how can these be transformed to produce a different ecology altogether.
I think, in a sense, we end up arriving at something like a process-ethics, in which we are constantly reevaluating and attenuating ourselves to transforming ecological processes, and are less able to firmly stand by transcendental ethical truths or neatly assign responsibility in any sort of resolved way.
I have a (very) rough draft of a paper on this topic if you’d be interested in taking a look.
Best,
~i
September 13, 2013 at 9:56 pm
Great stuff! I was reminded of those passages from Spinoza right after I responded to you. I raised those questions because I think many of the discussions of ethics I encounter in contemporary continental thought are incredibly vague and underdeveloped. For example, while finding Levinas very beautiful (especially at the literary level), I also think he’s almost entirely useless for concrete ethical and political thought. I think you’re right that we need something of a posthuman resurrection of Epicurean and Stoic thought (perhaps even Aristotlean virtue ethics) read through the lens of Spinoza’s antihumanist ethics.
September 14, 2013 at 3:54 am
Do you see affinities here with Popper too? I’m thinking of his acknowledged debt to the Epicureans, his strong stand against teleology in politics, his concept of a “piecemeal” legal system — all of which seem to be shot through with an ecological ethics.
September 18, 2013 at 5:25 pm
[…] I’ve been out of the game for a while now, but a recent post by Levi Bryant over at Larval Subjects has moved me to say a thing or two on the possibility of an ecologically sensitive ethics and […]
September 19, 2013 at 12:21 pm
[…] while back there was a post from Levi Bryant on ethics and politics without Nature. And an interesting response was posted over at the Synthetic Zero blog on ethics and politics in […]
September 19, 2013 at 3:08 pm
[…] this blog and my old blog if you’re interested. The most recent contributions come from Levi Bryant and Michael at Synthetic_Zero. I find their cases compelling, and only want to add a little more […]
September 20, 2013 at 7:59 pm
[…] Ecological Ethics (larvalsubjects.wordpress.com) […]