raphael_athens_platoOver at Now-Times, Alexei has written a post criticizing the central claim of the Ontic Principle. In response to some questions Alexei had over at Perverse Egalitarianism, I had evoked my Ontological Principle and wrote,

One of the strange things about the ontology I’m trying to develop is that anything that produces a difference would be included under the umbrella of the real. Consequently, insofar as concepts contribute differences– and often very important differences –they would, for me, be included under the real. I take it that this is one of the consequences of what I’ve called the Ontological Principle, which states that being is said in a single and same sense for all that is, i.e., being is univocal. Consequently, in my ontology, there is not one world that is “really real” like, say, physical objects, and another world that is not really real like, say, minds. Both are really real insofar as they contribute differences.

In short, the Ontological Principle asserts that if something is a difference or makes a difference it is real, full stop. Or, put otherwise, being is said in a single and same sense for all that is. This, of course, leads to a very strange ontology, for it commits me to the thesis that, say, the world depicted in Neal Stephenson’s Anathem has a claim to being. Insofar as this world makes a difference, it would follow from my ontic principle that it is real.

read on!

I am not entirely certain I understand Alexei’s argument, so I’ll quote a couple of passages from his post and respond to them. Alexei writes,

Leaving aside the Spinozism of his last two sentences, I think Levi’s right to say that Concepts contribute to, or create differences. In fact, I think all of contemporary aesthetics is built on this claim — it’s the cornerstone for Danto’s whole aesthetics and ontology of art: the differentiation between art and non-art, as Danto argues in his the Transfiguration of the Commonplace is conceptual. Hence Warhol’s genius. His brillo box is art, for although it’s perceptually indistinguishable form a Real brillo box, it has a conceptually distinct physiognomy. What I’m wary about is Levi’s Occamite nominalism: the thing (in its broad sense) that announces a difference gains ontological status. What delineates Danto’s thought from the one Levi is pursuing is, ceteris paribus, that whereas art is a human activity and Danto’s ontology is a social ontology, Levi thinks that this distinction between social ontology and natural ontology is bogus. To irritate him, we could say: this difference (the difference between the Naturwissenschaften and the Geisteswissenschaften) isn’t a difference that makes a difference. So despite radically different research paradigms, interests, and theoretical objects, there’s no difference at the level of ontology.

On the one hand, if I follow Alexei’s argument, he seems to be charging me with a performative contradiction. That is, my Ontic Principle states that the minimal condition for being a being lies in difference. There is a difference between Naturwissenschaften and Geisteswissenschaften, so therefore I should be committed to the thesis that these two orders are real. However, my Ontological Principle states that being is said in a single and same sense for all that is. This collapses the difference between nature and culture, thereby contradicting the Ontic Principle. I am unclear, however, as to how this conclusion follows from the Ontological Principle. The Ontological Principle does not state that all beings are of the same sort, but that all differences are real. That is, to be is to differ. Insofar as difference differs, it thus follows that we must investigate the nature of these differences to see how they are organized and function. In other words, there is nothing in my ontology that prohibits the distinction between pure ontology and regional ontologies, insofar as regional ontologies would investigate particular fields of difference, whereas pure ontology would be largely exhausted by the thesis that to be is to differ and make difference.

What I find perplexing in Alexei’s formulation above is the implicit thesis that culture is not real, and that it is only nature that is real. In other words, Alexei seems to be advancing the thesis that only the physical is, whereas somehow the cultural is not. I do not see why this would be the case. I will, however, say that one of the things I’m trying to accomplish at the level of social and political theory is, following Latour, the introduction of non-human actors into social networks. In my view, a good deal of social and political thought suffers from flawed assumptions at the level of social ontology. The field gets restricted to human beings, discourses, signifiers, language, ideas, norms, etc., and the non-human is set aside and treated as something outside of or other than the social. Following Latour, my thesis would be that the inhuman is an actor in the social as well, and that the social cannot be adequately thought without taking into account non-human actors.

I learned of a good example non-human actors play in social assemblages or networks as an undergrad in a course entitled Nature, Technology, and Culture. There the professor discussed a city where the bridges between the North and South side were built too low for the public buses to pass through. This simple fact contributed a major difference in both income distribution and cultural distribution in the city, as those who were from the South side of the city could not readily travel to the North side of the city where many of the jobs were. In addition, this difference, the bridge, had both catalytic and de-catalytic effects in the sorts of human networks formed. By virtue of this lack of ready transportion between the North and South sides, networks among humans became restricted to these particular regions, leading these networks to become self-reinforcing of particular relationships. In this example, the simple height of the bridge would be a non-human actor within the social assemblage. It will be objected that the bridges were built by human hands, that they would not exist without humans, and this would be true. However, the key point is that the difference introduced by the height of the bridges was not– as far as we know —intended to produce this difference.

landsat_chadSimilarly, we have completely inhuman actors that play a significant role in processes of social assembly. Thus, for example, what role does the disappearance of Lake Chad, an inhuman entity, play in the process of assembly for human relations in Africa? Lake Chad is an inhuman actor that certainly plays a significant role in how life is organized among people in this region. Through the role of this actor, people are led to relate to the land differently, each other differently, occupations differently, and perhaps even their cultural beliefs differently. As a result of the way in which this lake acts, all sorts of translations must take place among the people in this vicinity.

In short, my thesis would be that the social is composed not of what is human, but of the inhuman and human alike. Once again, following Latour, this leads to a significant transformation of our understanding of the social. The social is not a distinct substance in opposition to, say, the natural or the psychological. Rather, the social now refers to associations. Following Whitehead, the social will thus refer to any form of association, whether completely inhuman or involving combinations of the human and the inhuman. What will be of interest in a social theory is how these association are made and remade. As Latour dramatically puts it, “the social does not explain but must be explained”… No groups only group formations. The point that inhuman actors play a significant role in human social formations might appear trite and obvious– and it really should be –but when confronting a world of social and political theory that seems to focus almost entirely on the discursive, the symbolic, and the normative, it is, I think, a tremendously important point to make. So long as these inhuman actors are not included in associations or assemblages, I just don’t see how we can pose the right sort of questions. George Bush states the terrorists are out to get us because they hate our way of life, i.e., culture is to explain it all. There are no small number of theorists who make similar claims in much more elaborate and sophisticated vocabularies. The point is not that culture, language, signs, history, etc., do not make a difference, but that we must also think these differences in their relation to inhuman differences.

Alexei goes on to write:

Synthetically rephrased: Levi selectively emphasizes difference. And I take this to be a paradox, one that Mikhail caught a fair amount of flak for articulating in the course of his Downer Principle. Now, unless Levi can somehow (1) rein in the cascade of conceptual differences that make a difference, say between ‘Nature’ and ‘culture,’ there’s no grounds for making distinctions or identifying differences in the first place. But that means that not every difference can ultimately be treated as an ontological entitity, at least in Levi’s robust sense.

This implies, moreover, (2) figuring out conceptually how concepts can contribute to or create difference, without themselves being ontologically central. This latter point is a corollary of the more consistent Copernicanism that characterizes Object Oriented Philosophy: Subjectivity — that begets all concepts — is not the Centre of Ontology, and hence it’s resources — concepts — cannot be central to the ontological. Mikhail announced versions of these criticisms earlier. And I think that were the two of us particularly churlish, we could write a very Platonic dialogue, akin to the Parmenides and the Sophist, to show why you don’t want to endorse Levi’s Occamite nominalism: this ontlogy of concepts always engenders inconsistency.

Here, once again, I think Alexei conflates the ontological issue with the epistemic issue (understandable given his correlationist commitments). For Alexei, the issue is one of identifying important differences and making distinctions. I do not at all deny that humans identify differences and make distinctions. A scientist practicing physics, for example, says “let’s ignore all the qualitative differences in a physical object such as its color, its taste, etc. and restrict ourselves to examining the relationship between its mass and velocity”. That same scientist also develops concepts that allow him to identify and distinguish qualities and these other properties. These distinctions and identifications pertain to what the scientist wishes to know about the world. This is even demanded by my Ontic Principle. If it is true that all differences make a difference, then we need to include human differences as well. This is one major way in which my position differs from that of the Speculative Realists. Where the Speculative Realist claims that we can only attain the real by thinking a world without humans, I include humans among the real things in the universe.

There is thus nothing in my ontology to prevent making distinctions, identifying things, excluding certain things as irrelevant to inquiry, etc. All of these are crucial for any sort of investigation. The ontological point is simply that if something is it both contains difference and makes a difference. Thus, my thesis is three-fold: First, I do not hold that the human-world relation is the central or key relation to ontology. Relationships between humans and other objects are one relation among many other relations that don’t include humans at all. Second, I hold that ontology ought to be able to talk about objects and relations that share no relation to the human whatsoever (though admittedly I’m not sure how this is possible). Third, just as a matter of philosophical ethics, I think it would be a tremendous improvement if it were simply granted that all differences make a difference, thereby opening a space in which a variety of factors can be seen to play a role. Thus, at the level of epistemology, I can perfectly well concede that for the sake of my particular inquiry or investigation I am going to restrict myself to the role that technology places in human assemblages. However, in making this methodological exclusion, I need not jump to the ontological conclusion that for social assemblages economics is unimportant, signifiers are unimportant, history is unimportant, etc. Where the technology studies person might illicitly confuse their particular region of investigation with the ontological essence of the subject, thereby dismissing the Marxist economist, this minimal acknowledgment of how difference functions might allow us to achieve a both/and perspective rather than an either/or perspective while acknowledging our very real incapacity to examine all differences. In doing so, this minimal admission would help to halt futile and silly debates.

Alexei ends his critique on a note that I just don’t understand. Alexei writes:

Appealing to Danto might be a nice way to illustrate this. For Danto, art is essentially and from the beginning a conceptual activity. So it’s not like there’s a work of art to which we apply a set of concepts post festum. There’s no real ancestral relationship. and hence our ability to create art and our aesthetic concepts are equiprimordial. Levi’s claim is different. Things are ontological, levi contends, in virtue of their ability to produce differences. Concepts, however, come late. They are effects of differences that can, in their turn, produce or identify other differences. Despite their ability to identify or produce differences, concepts are not equiprimordial with other differences, since they don’t have the same ancestral relationships, and hence don’t inhabit the same plane or level of ontological consideration. I suppose this is a version of Spinozistic parallelism, but who on earth was ever happy with this argument in Spinoza?

Here Alexei’s reference to the ancestral thoroughly perplexes me. I am unclear as to why the fact that something comes late in any way diminishes its being or its reality. The idea seems to be that in order for something to be it must always already have existed. Yet life comes late and is. Certain forms of society come late and nonetheless are, etc. My Principle of Irreduction states that nothing is either reducible or irreducible to anything else. The fact that concepts emerge or are products in no way diminishes the reality of those concepts and their capacity to produce differences. All that is being claimed is that conceptual differences are not involved in the being of all entities. The rock on the mountain gets along just fine without them. I would also disagree that our ability to create art and our aesthetic concepts are equiprimordial for the reasons I outlined in my previous post, “Correlationism”. Rather, I would hold that there is a field of singularities that generate forms and am committed to the thesis that art and aesthetic concepts can change significantly over time as a result of these processes of genesis.

Once again, I’d like to express my deep gratitude towards Alexei for the manner in which he’s approached this discussion. Rather than approaching this discussion as a matter of misinterpretation or textual dispute, he’s instead taken my claims seriously as philosophical claims– even if poorly developed –and responded to them with philosophical criticisms. I suspect that Alexei and I will not reach agreement, but both of us will benefit in sharpening our arguments and concepts nonetheless. This is the way to do it.